Tom Waldman, from the Department of Politics, PRDU recently gave a talk at the
Belfer Centre for Science and International Affairs, Harvard University.
Tom is
the recent author of War, Clausewitz and the Trinity (Ashgate).
Here
Tom explains why Clausewitz’s famous dictum – ‘war is a continuation of
politics by other means’ – embraces a complexity and depth that is often
missed.
"Two
hundred years ago, in early May 1813, a 32 year old Prussian officer was recovering
from wounds sustained only days earlier during the chaotic Battle of Lutzen. He
had led repeated cavalry charges as part of the allied German and Russian forces
confronting Napoleon’s Grand Army. At one point, finding himself surrounded by
French soldiers, he had had to fight his way out in desperate hand to hand
combat. Also, his face was blackened from frostbite having spent the winter
pursuing French forces during their disastrous retreat from Moscow, and he had personally
witnessed the dreadful crossing of the Berezina River. This soldier was Carl
von Clausewitz.
Why is it that still
even today, senior figures such as Colin Powell and General McChrystal publicly
invoke the ideas of this man? I will try and shed light on this question.
My
central argument is simple: that the meaning of Clausewitz’s
famous dictum – ‘war is a continuation of politics by other means’ – embraces a
great deal of complexity and depth that is all too often missed. Clausewitz’s aphorism
appears almost everywhere, but often only in passing, and it’s often mistakenly
represented as the totality of his theorising, or used out of context in a simplistic sense. So, for instance, Martin van Creveld could claim that
Clausewitz believed war was ‘a rational instrument for the attainment of
rational social ends’.
However,
in recent years there has since been something of a renaissance in Clausewitz
studies and I think what we are seeing is a shift from the idea of the
primacy of policy to the primacy of politics.
Clausewitz stated that, ‘Nothing is more important in life than finding the
right standpoint for seeing and judging events, and then addressing them.’ War
as a continuation of politics,
properly understood, was for him precisely that standpoint.
I
argue that there are three key political perspectives of war in Clausewitz’s
thought.
First, political conditions essentially provide the broad context and
give meaning and form to the other two perspectives. For Clausewitz, political
conditions represented the ‘womb of war’ from which it emerges; it largely
explains the ways group fight, who they fight and, indeed, the objects they
fight for. Second, war’s subordination to policy presents a unilateral,
subjective perspective, and it is from this perspective that most of the
mistaken assumptions of pure rationality derive. Here it is important to distinguish
between Clausewitz’s prescriptive insights and those that simply seek to
describe the phenomenon. Clausewitz claimed that in war there would be for the
actors involved a definite if messy interaction between ends and means, that
weaves a thread of reason through the whole, even if the tapestry hangs
together only loosely given the many barriers to perfect rationality that exist
in war.
Third,
there is often a failure in reading Clausewitz to progress from the subjective
idea of subordination to the wider implications of ‘continuation’. These two
perspectives are interwoven in On War.
In the crucial Chapter 6B of Book 8 of On
War, the transition from one perspective to the other is almost missed. To
take just one instance of this, he states, ‘When whole communities go to war
the reason always lies in some political
situation, and the occasion is always due to some political object. War, therefore, is an act of policy.’
So,
essentially for Clausewitz war is both a continuation of the interactive
political situation and the
instrument employed by the actors that make up that situation. The two
perspectives are inseparable and implicated in the meaning of the other.
‘Continuation’ thus embraces all three perspectives that I have identified and
serves as holistic means of understanding the relationship between politics and
war: war is a continuation of a multidimensional political situation comprised
of the competing policies of those involved, both of which are shaped in
important ways by preexisting political conditions.
There
are four theoretical implications emerging from this.
First, war can never be
understood as autonomous but is always part of a wider whole, which is politics
– war is itself a form of political behaviour, only it employs different means.
Second, war is ensconced within a perpetually shifting ‘political web
of war’ – the multitude of actors and relationships within, between and beyond
belligerents.
Third, during war there will be a continuous, simultaneous and
non-linear reciprocal feedback between the use of force, politics and policy.
Fourth, understanding the psychology of the politics of war brings all these
perspectives and implications together – the role of perceptions are crucial to
understanding the political effects of the use of force. War does not contain in itself the elements for a final
settlement, but beyond situations where the enemy is completely destroyed
(which is very rare), the enemy must be persuaded
to submit. This all underlines the often ambiguous nature of military victory
and the way in which politics has an unnerving habit of delivering its own
verdict on events.
The
complexity of the politics of war is too often ignored by theorists and
commanders alike: war is conceived as unilateral, autonomous, linear, material
and rationally controllable. It might be said that much of this is obvious,
common-sense, maybe even banal. I would argue, in many respects it is. But it
is staggering how often these basic points are forgotten or ignored. In Iraq and Afghanistan, Western states have
struggled to employ their militaries as effective instruments of policy, and primarily
I would argue due to political myopia, rather than to any major military
shortcomings.
Force
has often been employed as if in a political vacuum; little attempt has been
made to understand the enemy, it’s objectives, character or psychology; policy has
been incoherent, short-termist and introspective; political actors have failed
to properly understand the wars they oversee or provide clear guidance as to
objectives; the military has therefore dominated strategic decision-making in
what are intensely political situations; and instruments of force have been
used for their own sake, simply because they are available. And interestingly, what
course corrections have taken place have primarily been of a political nature:
the Sunni Awakening; the move towards reconciliation in Afghanistan and so
forth. Most regrettably, troops on the ground have been repeatedly let down by
strategic ineptitude and their efforts not translated into meaningful political
effect.
The complexity of Clausewitz’s terse dictum calls for the
sophisticated socio-political understanding and psychological intuition of genius
– Clausewitz states that even ‘Newton himself would quail before the algebraic
problems it could pose’. However, given that war is always an interactive
phenomenon, perhaps the only real comfort is that the political genius required
only needs be relative, not absolute. That Clausewitz recognised the
fundamentally complex political nature of war in an age dominated by the
annihilation battle is, I think, testament to his own remarkable genius".
No comments:
Post a Comment